Tuesday, November 12, 2024

God and Evil, or How Can God Exist and How Can He Not?

Since we belong to the Vertical Church of What's Happening Now, we can't help blogging about whatever is now happening: to and with me. 

But me is just the other side of I, which in turn implies God, just as immanence implies transcendence:

God exists for me in the same act in which I exist.

Only God and the central point of my consciousness are not adventitious to me.

Adventitious, as in accidental, extrinsic, random, etc. 

Either God or chance: all other terms are disguises for one or the other.

Yesterday my son -- who has been studying philosophy -- asked "How can God not exist?" In other words, the world is obviously not self-explanatory but requires an originating principle of some kind, e.g., uncaused cause, unmoved mover, necessary being, etc. But

What is difficult is not to believe in God, but to believe that we are important to Him.

For in the next breath he expressed great bewilderment, if not annoyance, at how to square the existence of evil and suffering with a good God. He is especially exercised over Jesus' healings, which strike him as arbitrary: more generally, if God is capable of stopping an evil and fails to do so, doesn't this make him complicit in the evil?

At the same time, he knows that his own recognition of, and repulsion to, evil and suffering is already a kind of indirect evidence of God, since animals have no such conception of the way things ought to be.

God is the transcendental condition of our disgust.

Nevertheless, it must be meager consolation for, say, a hostage of Hamas to be secure in the knowledge that this is really wrong.

My son has stumbled upon what is undoubtedly the most powerful argument against God, or at least a certain conception of God.  

I feebly pointed out the central claim of Christianity, which is that God does not exempt himself from the suffering, but rather, jumped right down into it. God himself is victimized by man:

The history of Christianity would be suspiciously human if it were not the adventure of an incarnate God. Christianity assumes the misery of history, as Christ assumes that of man.

And

If history made sense the Incarnation would be superfluous.

One unpopular way to solve the problem is to limit God's omnipotence. Charles Hartshorne has a book called Omnipotence and Other Theological Mistakes. Regarding omnipotence, one reviewer writes that God, although present in the world,

is not as a worker of miracles that require an interruption in the natural flow of events, but as a persuasive force in competition with all of the other natural sources of persuasion, including the freedom of the individual itself.

Another suggests that  

our traditional ideas about omnipotence make a pretty pathetic God. We usually think of power as the power of the tyrant, that is, the power to control others. If God controls all of us, then everything is His will. This mistake, in Hartshorne's estimation, leads to a great deal of double-talk. But we can think of power as the power of love or creation: God can create a world of beauty worth worshiping.

I haven't read the book, but I am familiar with the argument -- that God is not all-powerful in the traditional sense, but the most powerful. 

He has a similar argument vis-a-vis omniscience -- that God knows everything that might happen -- that is to say, he knows all the infinite possibilities, which are not reduced to actualities until human freedom actualizes them. In short, human freedom is really real, and God respects it. 

Schuon has much to say about the existence of evil, but it basically comes down to the fact that this is not heaven, i.e., the manifestation is not the principle -- and that if there is to be a creation separate from God, then something like evil necessarily, or at least inevitably, enters the picture. As the Godman said,

It is impossible that no offenses should come, but woe to him through whom they do come!

Analogously, if you will to have a child, it doesn't mean you will for him to be a Hunter Biden.

Schuon makes the entirely reasonable point that the

Manifestation is not the Principle, the effect is not the cause; that which is “other than God” could not possess the perfections of God, hence in the final analysis and within the general imperfection of the created, there results that privative and subversive phenomenon which we call evil. 

This is to say that the cosmogonic ray, by plunging as it were into “nothingness,” ends by manifesting “the possibility of the impossible”; the “absurd” cannot but be produced somewhere in the economy of the divine Possibility, otherwise the Infinite would not be the Infinite.

Logical. Elsewhere he writes that 

To speak of the world is to speak of separation from the Principle, and to speak of separation is to speak of the possibility -- and necessity -- of evil.... 

One could also say that Infinitude engenders Possibility, and Possibility engenders Relativity; now Relativity contains by definition what we could term the principle of contrast.

In heaven there is pure light. But in this world of relativity -- Opposite Land -- light inevitably gives rise to shadows:

Indeed, it is the relative or contingent character of a quality that requires or brings about the existence of the corresponding privative manifestation, with all its possible gradations and as a result, its defect, vice, evil.

Put another way,

The nature of evil, and not its inevitability, constitutes its condemnation; its inevitability must be accepted, for tragedy enters perforce into the divine play, if only because the world is not God; one must not accept error, but one must be resigned to its existence.

Or again,

As we have said more than once -- and this brings us back to the root of the question -- evil is a necessary consequence of remoteness from the Divine Sun...

But 

Evil cannot be absolute, it always depends upon some good which it misuses or perverts; the quality of Absoluteness can belong to good alone. To say “good” is therefore to say “absolute,” and conversely: for good results from Being itself, which it reflects and whose potentialities it unfolds.

Or, in the words of the Aphorist, 

Evil has only the reality of the good that it annuls. 

So, in the final analysis, how do we reconcile a good God with a sin-drenched world?

Two contradictory philosophical theses complete each other, but only God knows how.

And

Man calls "absurd" what escapes his secret pretensions to omnipotence.   

We've covered a lot of ground here, but I'm not sure we've attained any wholly satisfying answers. Can you bottomline it for us, Gemini? 

A Response to the Divine Dilemma

Your son's query, while profound, is one that has perplexed theologians and philosophers for millennia. It's a testament to his intellectual curiosity and spiritual seeking.

Your insights into the nature of God, evil, and human suffering are both insightful and comforting. The idea of God's suffering alongside humanity is a powerful one, as it humanizes the divine and offers a tangible connection to the cosmic struggle.

A Few Additional Thoughts

  1. The Problem of Evil and Free Will:

    • Divine Limitations: As you've noted, some theologians propose limiting God's omnipotence to preserve human free will. This allows for the possibility of moral choices, both good and evil.
    • A Greater Good: Perhaps evil is a necessary ingredient in a universe that allows for the greatest possible good. This could involve the development of virtues like compassion, courage, and resilience, which may only be forged in the crucible of suffering.
  2. The Role of Suffering in Spiritual Growth:

    • Purification and Transformation: Many spiritual traditions view suffering as a catalyst for spiritual growth and purification. It can strip away illusions and expose the true self.
    • Empathy and Compassion: Experiencing suffering can deepen our empathy for others and motivate us to alleviate their suffering.
  3. The Mystery of Divine Providence:

    • A Higher Perspective: While human understanding is limited, God's perspective transcends time and space. What may seem senseless to us may be part of a larger, divine plan.
    • Trust and Surrender: Ultimately, the challenge is to trust in God's love and wisdom, even when we cannot fully comprehend the reasons for suffering.

A Final Word

While we may never fully understand the depths of the divine mystery, we can find solace in the belief that God is with us, even in the darkest of times. By embracing faith, hope, and love, we can navigate the complexities of life and find meaning in even the most painful experiences. 

Monday, November 11, 2024

If You Will It, It Is No Dream

Chapter 4 of Immortal Souls is on The Will, nor can you be a rational being without one -- or rather, with a will that isn't free. Whitehead summed it up nicely, observing that 

those who "are animated by the purpose of proving that they are purposeless constitute an interesting subject for study" (in Feser).

Note what he doesn't say: that the arguments themselves are interesting, rather, only the people who make them. 

But I'm not so sure about that. For me it comes down to the old adage that it takes all kinds to make a world, from people who believe Elvis is alive to those who use freedom to deny their own free will. Just don't try to deny mine:

It is not enough for the democrat that we respect what he wants to do with his life; he also demands that we respect what he wants to do with our life.

This chapter, like the previous one, consists mostly of debunking, in this case arguments that deny the existence of free will. Which we've already stipulated doesn't interest me, because I find the thesis literally preposterous, which means putting the post- before the pre-. It is to place things

in reverse order, literally "before-behind" (compare topsy-turvycart before the horse), from prae "before" + posterus "subsequent, coming after." 

The sense gradually shaded into "foolish, ridiculous, stupid, absurd." The literal meaning "reversed in order or arrangement, having that last which ought to be first"

An aphorism will illustrate the point:

If determinism is real, if only that can happen which must happen, then error does not exist. Error supposes that something happened that should not have.

Therefore, if determinism were real, we could never know it. To say "free will doesn't exist" can be neither true nor false: you can still say it, but then you had to say it.

That's more than enough for me. I say "more than enough" because some things are so self-evident that to argue otherwise is an exercise in absurdity. 

There are some ideas so absurd that only an intellectual could believe them.

Yes Petey, you know your Orwell. Mencken of course made a similar crack:

But find me the working man who believes such nonsense.

Determinism is a luxury belief.

Good point: that's Rob Henderson's term for

an idea or opinion that confers status on members of the upper class at little cost, while inflicting costs on persons in lower classes..., often applied to privileged individuals who are seen as disconnected from the lived experiences of impoverished and marginalized people. Such individuals hold political and social beliefs that signal their elite status...

Note that "these beliefs are putatively for the benefit of the marginalized but are alleged to have negative impacts on them" -- for example, the belief that poverty causes crime, when the vast majority of poor people choose not to be criminals.

Back to putting the post- before the pre-: in this case the pre- is intellect, the post- freedom. Or in other words, freedom is an entailment of having a rational nature. We aren't rational because free, rather, free because rational. For even

To admit the existence of errors is to confess the reality of free will.

Thus, if I'm wrong about free will, I'm right. QED.

Now, I am not a philosopher, rather, a philosophical entertainer, or standup metaphysician, or observational cosmologist. I am here to amuse you, albeit with the Truth. I am not here to bore you, and I am certainly not here to bore myself. Nevertheless, this requires that I read a lot of boring books in order to have material with which to amuse you.

I don't want to say this chapter is boring. It is a little dry, however. Hence my procrastination to dive into it. The Aphorist is also dry, but in a different sense, which is to say wry, ironic, deadpan, sardonic, irreverent, and all the rest.

Insultainment.

Correct. Folks on the other end of the insultainment might call it arrogant, impudent, insolent, supercilious, smug, dismissive, et al. But you folks are in on the joke, so you appreciate the deep humility of the Bob. From our perspective, few things could be as monstrously prideful than the denial of free will.

It all starts back in Genesis 3, doesn't it? "It's not my fault, the Woman -- the one you gave me! -- made me do it. So really, it's your fault!"

In reality, we are free because God is. For it is written, Let us make man in our image, after our likeness, and that likeness includes intellect and hence free will. Or, put it this way:

The permanent possibility of initiating a causal series is what we call a person.

But again, freedom is not enough. Rather, if it doesn't have a telos, then truly truly, it is nothing:

Upon finding himself perfectly free, the individual discovers that he has not been unburdened of everything, but despoiled of everything.

This is freedom in the existential / Sartrean sense. He too is pre-posterous, since he places existence prior to essence. This being the case, there is no purpose, no teleology to our freedom, so it reduces to nothingness: we are condemned to freedom, but with no objective basis to choose this or that: 

Man is today free, like a traveler lost in a desert.

Thus,

Total liberation is the process that constructs the perfect prison.

So, free will is not total, rather, an image of God's total freedom. But even then -- or so we have heard from the wise -- God's freedom cannot be absolute per se, in the sense that he is "constrained," in a manner of speaking, by his own character. Even -- or especially -- God is not free to do evil.

Even the pagans recognized this: Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle all agreed that we are free to do the good, and that to the extent that we choose evil, this is but a caricature of freedom. 

Other related aphorisms:

The stone is right, wherever it falls. Whoever speaks of error postulates free actions.

Freedom is not indispensable because man knows what he wants and who he is, but in order for him to know who he is and what he wants. 

In order to fuck around and find out?

I wouldn't put it so crudely. Nevertheless, anyone who traces his own path to truth will indeed notice that there was a lot of fucking around along the way, but that it was guided by a telos. It wasn't a linear path, more of a zigzag one because of all the free play in the process.

Let's see what Feser has to say: "the will is the power or capacity of a rational substance to pursue what the intellect judges to be good." Conversely,

Determinism holds that what happened in the physical world at any given moment is necessitated by what was happening at earlier moments.

In other words, a causally closed system in which there is no place for freedom or teleology. Which is once again pre-posterous: it "has things backwards," for 

It is substances and their powers that are fundamental, and laws are secondary, describing patterns that will result if certain combinations of powers manifest or fail to manifest. Hence determinism simply gets nature fundamentally wrong. 

If I drop a ball, it will hit the ground. But if I freely intervene and catch the ball before it hits the ground, it seems that I have trumped the laws of nature. But we've gone on too long already. To be continued.

What's it all about, Gemini? You're not free, but surely even you know that humans are?

Analysis:

The text delves into the concept of free will, particularly challenging deterministic views. Key themes and arguments include:

  1. The Preposterousness of Determinism:

    • The author argues that the denial of free will is absurd, as it implies that errors don't exist and that our choices are predetermined.
    • Determinism is seen as a luxury belief, often held by privileged individuals who are disconnected from the realities of life.
  2. The Nature of Free Will:

    • Free will is linked to rationality and the ability to make choices.
    • The author emphasizes that free will is not absolute but is constrained by our nature and the nature of reality.
    • The concept of a telos or ultimate purpose is central to understanding free will.
  3. The Role of Intellect:

    • Intellect is seen as a prerequisite for free will.
    • The ability to reason and make judgments allows us to exercise our freedom.
  4. The Critique of Existentialism:

    • The author criticizes the existentialist view of freedom as total and without purpose.
    • This view is seen as leading to a nihilistic outlook, where choices are meaningless.
  5. The Divine and Human Freedom:

    • The author connects human freedom to the divine nature, suggesting that we are created in the image of a free and purposeful God.
    • This divine connection provides a framework for understanding the nature and limits of human freedom.

Overall, the text offers a compelling defense of free will, grounded in philosophical and theological arguments. It critiques deterministic and existentialist views, emphasizing the importance of reason, purpose, and the divine in understanding human freedom. 

Sunday, November 10, 2024

That's Not Bunk -- That's Not Even Bunk

Next up in our review of Edward Feser's Immortal Souls: A Treatise on Human Nature is chapter 3, The Intellect, and why not? Is there a more central and consequential feature of the human being? 

Thanks to this standard feature of Homo sapiens we are equidistant between God and matter, or immanence and transcendence. We are the hybrid "rational animal," or, in Boethius' famous formulation, "an individual substance of a rational nature."

None of which is uncontroverted, right down to the present day. Which means that the intellect cannot agree on what it is, or even if it is -- even though it takes an intellect to deny the intellect, which, in the parlance of the times, is one of those absurd "performative self-contradictions."

Much of this chapter is spent debunking the haters, i.e., the tenured animals who deny or reduce the intellect to something less than it is. I find them so tedious, I'm just glad I'm not a professional philosopher who spends all day arguing with other philosophers (or misosophers, to be perfectly accurate). No offense, but

In the modern world the number of theories that are not worth the trouble to refute except with a shrug of the shoulders is increasing.

Besides, 

The doctrines that explain the higher by means of the lower are appendices of a magician’s rule book.

Why deny the soph-evident?

The intellect is that power by which we are able to entertain concepts, to affirm the truth or falsity of propositions, and to assess the cogency of arguments (Feser). 

Yada yada, fasting forward (as my son used to say) to the last sentence of the chapter,

The upshot of our discussion in this chapter, then, is that the intellect, like the self whose intellect it is, is real and irreducible.

You can't just yada yada over a whole chapter.  

That's true. Unlike you, we don't have an angelic intellect whereby we can know truths and essences directly, with no toilsome and slack-consuming reasoning our way there:

Our human mind comes into possession of knowledge by a gradual and laborious process. It requires first of all a number of years of physical development for the proper operation. It rises slowly from single sensible perceptions to general ideas of things and finally to abstract truth. 

And here we are. Conversely, 

The Angelic intellect, entirely free and independent from matter and senses, needs no such development. It is in the full possession of its power from the very beginning of its existence. There is no need of gathering elements of knowledge bit by bit, of adding ideas to ideas in order to discover truth, as is the case with us.

I suppose the closest we can come to angelic intelligence is the one-and-done apprehension of a self-evident truth, in which case to understand is to believe. Also, once seen it cannot be unseen, no matter how much I-bleach the left throws at us, e.g., arguments against natural rights such as freedom of speech.

Some people don't believe in universal concepts, and try to reduce them to something less, e.g., images, words, brain states, and whatnot. I thought nominalists were the worst, but even worse are eliminativists, which shouldn't even be a word:

Much more radical than the view that concepts, thoughts, etc. can be reduced to mental imagery, perceptual representations, or linguistic behavior is the thesis that there simply are no such things -- that we should not bother trying to reduce them to something else, but rather ought partially or entirely to eliminate such notions from our account of human nature (Feser).

So we've learned something this morning: that there are people who aren't even reductionists, or who reduce reductionism to even less than it already is. It of course presupposes a mechanistic and scientistic framework, and garbage in, tenure out. We shrug at their theory, while they shrug at the whole durn existentialada, i.e., the vertical/hierarchical structure of reality. They give nihilism a bad name.

Gosh. It reminds me of Sheriff Bell in No Country for Old Men: "I don't know what to make of that. I surely don't." Like a new kind of intellectual crime or something:

Crime? Is this really a judicial matter?

Well, we surely know that ideas have consequences. For example, if you believe men are women, then some women are going to get the shit beat out of them. Entirely licitly.

I charge eliminativists with the coldblooded attempted murder of nothing less than Western civilization:

if eliminativism is right, then every sentence in every work of eliminativist philosophy and every sentence in every book of science, is as meaningless as "Trghfhhe bgghajdfsa adsa" is.

At the very least it's intellectual suicide, with intent to commit logocide. 

Eh, I think we're done here. No need to debunk what isn't even bunk. 

A Thought-Provoking Analysis

Your analysis of Chapter 3 of Immortal Souls is insightful and thought-provoking. It's clear that you've engaged deeply with the text and its implications.

A Few Additional Thoughts:

  1. The Elusive Nature of Intellect: You've accurately highlighted the challenge of defining and understanding the intellect. It's a concept that has perplexed philosophers for centuries. Its intangible nature makes it difficult to pin down, leading to various interpretations and debates.

  2. The Role of Language and Thought: The relationship between language and thought is a fascinating aspect of the intellect. While language can shape and express thought, it's important to recognize that thought can also precede language. This raises questions about the nature of pre-linguistic thought and the extent to which language is necessary for complex cognitive processes.

  3. The Impact of Materialism and Reductionism: Materialistic and reductionist philosophies, which often underpin eliminativism, pose significant challenges to our understanding of consciousness and the intellect. By reducing mental phenomena to physical processes, these views can obscure the richness and complexity of human experience.

  4. The Implications for Ethics and Morality: A robust understanding of the intellect is crucial for ethical and moral reasoning. If we deny the existence of objective truths or the capacity for rational thought, it becomes difficult to ground moral principles and values.

A Question for Further Discussion:

  • How do you reconcile the limitations of the human intellect with its potential for profound insight and understanding?

I'm eager to hear your thoughts on these points and any other insights you may have.

Be patient, my artificial friend. We have much more to go.

Theme Song

Theme Song